1. Having read the chapter on philosophy before Socrates and learned about the branches of philosophy, which of the four branches would you say was their primary focus or concern? Give three examples...

1 answer below »

1. Having read the chapter on philosophy before Socrates and learned about the branches of philosophy, which of the four branches would you say was their primary focus or concern? Give three examples of why you believe your answer accurately summarizes the primary focus of pre-Socratic philosophy.



2. As you read the "simplistic answer they had" (compared to the complex answer science has given us), do you think that they should , like myths, be understood literally? or should we assume some level of analogy and allegory?Example, for Thales everything is made of water and all things are filled with gods.


3. The author of the gospel of St. John, from the bible, began his book by using the term "word" (logos) to describe who Jesus is. Comparing the LOGOS of Heraclitus with the God of theism (Christianity, Judaism and Islam), do you find any similarities?




1 Presocratic Philosophy First published Sat Mar 10, 2007 The Presocratics were 6th and 5th century BCE Greek thinkers who introduced a new way of thinking about the world and the place of human beings in it. They were recognized in antiquity as the first philosophers and scientists of the Western tradition. This article is a general introduction to the most important Presocratic philosophers and the main themes of Presocratic thought... The standard collection of texts for the Presocratics is that by H. Diels revised by W. Kranz (abbreviated as DK). In it, each thinker is assigned an identifying chapter number (e.g., Heraclitus is 22, Anaxagoras 59); then the reports from ancient authors about that thinker's life and thought are collected in a section of ―testimonies‖ (A) and numbered in order, while the passages the editors take to be direct quotations are collected and numbered in a section of ―fragments‖ (B). Alleged imitations in later authors are sometimes added in a section labeled C. Thus, each piece of text can be uniquely identified: DK 59B12.3 identifies line 3 of Anaxagoras fragment 12; DK 22A1 identifies testimonium 1 on Heraclitus. 1. Who Were the Presocratic Philosophers? Our understanding of the Presocratics is complicated by the incomplete nature of our evidence. Most of them wrote at least one ―book‖ (short pieces of prose writing, it seems, or, in some cases, poems of not great length), but no complete work survives. Instead, we are dependent on later philosophers, historians, and compilers of collections of ancient wisdom for disconnected quotations (fragments) and reports about their views (testimonia). In some cases, these sources had direct access to the works of the Presocratics, but in many others, the line is indirect and often depends on the work of Aristotle, Theophrastus, and other ancient philosophers who did have access. The sources for the fragments and testimonia made selective use of the material available to them, in accordance with their own special, and varied, interests in the early thinkers. (For analyses of the doxographic tradition, and the influence of Aristotle and Theophrastus on later sources, see Mansfeld 1999, Runia forthcoming, and Mansfeld and Runia 1997.) Although any account of a Presocratic thinker has to be a reconstruction, we should not be overly pessimistic about the possibility of reaching a historically responsible understanding of these early Greek thinkers. Calling this group ―Presocratic philosophers‖ raises certain difficulties. (The term was made current by Hermann Diels in the nineteenth century.) ―Presocratic,‖ if 2 taken strictly as a chronological term, is not quite accurate, for the last of them were contemporaneous with Socrates and even Plato. The term also may suggest that these thinkers are somehow inferior to Socrates and Plato, of interest only as their predecessors, and its suggestion of archaism may imply that philosophy only becomes interesting when we arrive at the classical period of Plato and Aristotle. Some scholars now deliberately avoid the term, but if we take it to refer to the early Greek thinkers who were not influenced by the views of Socrates, whether his predecessors or contemporaries, there is probably no harm in using it. (For discussions of the notion of Presocratic philosophy, see Long's introduction in Long 1999, Laks 2006, articles in Laks and Louguet 2002.) A second problem lies in referring to these thinkers as philosophers. That is almost certainly not how they could have described themselves. While it is true that Heraclitus says that ―those who are lovers of wisdom must be inquirers into many things‖ (22B35), the word he uses, philosophos, does not have the special sense that it acquires in the works of Plato and Aristotle, when the philosopher is contrasted with both the ordinary person and other experts, including the sophist (particularly in Plato), or in the resulting modern sense in which we can distinguish philosophy from physics or psychology; yet the Presocratics certainly saw themselves as set apart from the ordinary person and also from other thinkers (poets and historical writers, for example) who were their predecessors and contemporaries. As the fragment from Heraclitus shows, the early Greek philosophers thought of themselves as inquirers into many things, and the range of their inquiry was vast. They had views about the nature of the world, and these views encompass what we today call physics, chemistry, geology, meteorology, astronomy, embryology, and psychology (and other areas of natural inquiry), as well as theology, metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. In the earliest of the Presocratics, the Milesians, it can indeed be difficult to discern the strictly philosophical aspects of the views in the evidence available to us. Nevertheless, despite the danger of misunderstanding and thus underestimating these thinkers on account of anachronism, there is an important sense in which it is quite reasonable to refer to them as philosophers. That sense is inherent in Aristotle's view (see, e.g., Met. I, Phys. I, De Anima I): these thinkers were his predecessors in a particular sort of inquiry, and even though Aristotle thinks that they were all, for one reason or another, unsuccessful and even amateurish, he sees in them a similarity such that he can trace a line of continuity of both subject and method from their work to his own. The questions that the early Greek philosophers asked, the sorts of answers that they gave, and the views that they had of their own inquiries were the foundation for the development of philosophy as it came to be defined in the work of Plato and 3 Aristotle and their successors. Perhaps the fundamental characteristic is the commitment to explain the world of nature in terms of its own inherent principles. By contrast, consider the 7th century BCE poem of Hesiod, his Theogony (genealogy of the gods). Hesiod tells the traditional story of the Olympian gods, beginning with Chaos, a vague divine primordial entity or condition. From Chaos, a sequence of gods is generated, often by sexual congress, but sometimes no particular cause is given. Each divine figure that arises is connected with a part of the physical universe, so his theogony is also a cosmogony (an account of the generation of the world). The divinities (and the associated parts of the world) come to be and struggle violently among themselves; finally Zeus triumphs and establishes and maintains an order of power among the others who remain. Hesiod's world is one in which the major divinities are individuals who behave like super-human beings (Gaia or earth, Ouranos or sky, Cronos — an unlocated regal power, Zeus); some of the others are personified characteristics (e.g., blame, want). For the Greeks, the fundamental properties of divinity are immortality and power, and each of Hesiod's characters has these properties (even though in the story some are defeated, and seem to be destroyed). Hesiod's story is like a vast Hollywood-style family history, with envy, rage, love, and lust all playing important parts in the coming-to-be of the world as we know it. The earliest rulers of the universe are violently overthrown by their offspring (Ouranos is overthrown by Cronos, Cronos by Zeus). Zeus insures his continued power by swallowing his first consort Metis (counsel or wisdom); by this he prevents the predicted birth of rivals and acquires her attribute of wisdom (Works and Days 886–900). In a second poem, Works and Days, Hesiod pays more attention to human beings, telling the story of earlier, greater creatures who died out or were destroyed by themselves or Zeus. Humans were created by Zeus, are under his power, and are subject to his judgment and to divine intervention for either good or ill. (A good discussion of the Hesiodic myths in relation to Presocratic philosophy can be found in McKirahan 1994.) Hesiod's world, like Homer's, is one that is god-saturated, where the gods may intervene in all aspects of the world, from the weather to mundane particulars of human life, reaching into the natural world order from outside, in a way that humans must accept but cannot ultimately understand. The Presocratics reject this account, instead seeing the world as a kosmos, an ordered natural arrangement that is inherently intelligible and not subject to supra-natural intervention. A striking example is Xenophanes 21B32: ―And she whom they call Iris, this too is by nature cloud / purple, red, and greeny yellow to behold.‖ Iris, the rainbow, traditional messenger of the gods, is after all, not supra-natural, not a sign from the gods on 4 Olympus who are outside the natural world order; rather it is, in its essence, colored cloud. Calling the Presocratics philosophers also suggests that they share a certain outlook with one another; an outlook that is to be contrasted with that of other early Greek writers. Although scholars disagree about the extent of the divergence between the early Greek philosophers and their non-philosophical predecessors and contemporaries, it seems evident that Presocratic thought exhibits a significant difference not only in its understanding of the nature of the world, but also in its view of the sort of explanation of it that is possible. This is evident in Heraclitus. Although Heraclitus asserts that those who love wisdom must be inquirers into many things, inquiry alone is not sufficient. At 22B40 he rebukes four of his predecessors: ―Much learning does not teach understanding; else it would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again Xenophanes and Hecataeus.‖ Heraclitus' implicit contrast is with himself; in 22B1 he suggests that he alone truly understands all things, because he grasps the account that enables him to ―distinguish each thing in accordance with its nature‖ and say how it is. For Heraclitus there is an underlying principle that unites and explains everything. It is this that others have failed to see and understand. According to Heraclitus, the four have amassed a great deal of information — Hesiod was a traditional source of information about the gods, Pythagoras was renowned for his learning and especially views about how one ought to live, Xenophanes taught about the proper view of the gods and the
Answered Same DayJul 14, 2021

Answer To: 1. Having read the chapter on philosophy before Socrates and learned about the branches of...

Arunavo answered on Jul 15 2021
144 Votes
Last Name:      2
Name:
Professor:
Course:
Date:
Title: Presocratic Philosophy
Contents
Branches of Philosophy before Socrates    3
Analogy and Allegory vs. Myths    4
Similari
ties Between LOGOS of Heraclitus with the God of theism    4
Works Cited    6
Branches of Philosophy before Socrates
The Pre-Socratic philosophy, which is also known as Greek Philosophy has many branches. As discussed by Patra the first branch is Milesian, where the major focus of interest was over the measurement and explanation of the celestial and the terrestrial phenomena. However, the assumptions and the principles provided by them including Aristotle clearly were considered as the philosophical view because they were lacking specific arguments and statements to prove the views. Another example is that there is a difference among Thales and Aristotle regarding the explanation of matters of earth, including water. And lastly the difference in opinion regarding the explanation of air both by Thales and Anaximander (Lahteenoja). The second branch of philosophy rests on Xenophanes of Colophon, where he proposed a theology that we do not know whether there is any god or there are many gods, or there is any kind of hierarchy in this system. The three examples of this theology are the use of different animals such as ox, horses, or lions. In this theology it has also been supported that gods are ethical in nature, and they are omnipotent, omnibenevolent, or omniscient. And the third aspect of this theology is that it supported on the human knowledge and real facts, rather focusing on something vague in nature (Atanelishvili & Silagadze). The third branch of philosophy is the Pythagorean tradition, which started with Pythagoras, famous for studying numbers and geometrical relation with numbers. His views...
SOLUTION.PDF

Answer To This Question Is Available To Download

Related Questions & Answers

More Questions »

Submit New Assignment

Copy and Paste Your Assignment Here